The New Industrial State:
The New Industrial State
Princeton University Press, 2007 - Business &
Economics - 518 pages
With searing wit and incisive
commentary, John Kenneth Galbraith redefined America's
perception of itself in The New Industrial State, one of his
landmark works. The United States is no longer a
free-enterprise society, Galbraith argues, but a structured
state controlled by the largest companies. Advertising is the
means by which these companies manage demand and create
consumer "need" where none previously existed. Multinational
corporations are the continuation of this power system on an
international level. The goal of these companies is not the
betterment of society, but immortality through an
uninterrupted stream of earnings.
First published in 1967, The New Industrial State continues to
resonate today.
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
<http://abridge.me.uk/doku.php?id=the_new_industrial_state>
The New Industrial
State, John Kenneth Galbraith, 1972 (2nd ed), Harmondsworth: Penguin
Change in the economic sphere
has been very great in recent history. It is a curiosity that
although this is accepted, what has changed is perceived to be
strictly limited. For instance, the
essential features of American capitalism remain perfect
throughout.
The increasing application of
sophisticated technology to production is perhaps the most obvious change. The corporation used to be very much
the instrument of its owners,
now it is under professional and much less identifiable
management. The federal and state governments are now much more
active participants in the
economy, together accounting for 23 per cent of production
(1969). The state is perceived to be responsible
for maintaining aggregate demand within the economy at a high enough level
to ensure minimal unemployment through Keynesian measures.
Before World War II, serious recession was seen as a normal part
of the business cycle; since the war there have been only two
years in which output failed to expand.
Less frequently celebrated, there has been a vast increase in the human effort expended in
advertising. “In its cost and the
talent it commands, this activity is coming increasingly to
rival the effort devoted to the production of goods.”1) Union
membership is no longer increasing, having peaked at 25.2 per
cent of the workforce in 1956
and having declined since. There has been a large increase in
enrolment in higher education, and a somewhat lagging increase
in funding.
These changes should be seen holistically. In sum, they create the need and the opportunity for large industrial organisation. Economic
systems tend to converge on the
large, bureaucratic industrial
system. There shape is thus more determined by technology and
organisation than by ideology.
The traditional and
pedagogically convenient view of America as a free market
capitalist economy dominated by small firms with little capital
is a poor representative of a substantial part of the economy. It is a reasonable
description of many remaining industries, such as agriculture,
truck mines, painting, musical composition, much writing, the professions, some vice,
handicrafts, some retail trade and a large number of repairing,
cleaning, refurbishing, cosmetic and other household and
personal services. However, this is not the sector of the economy under change. The Industrial
System as we shall call it, consisting of 500-600 corporations
in sectors such as communications, production and distribution
of electricity, transportation, manufacturing and mining, much
retail trade and entertainment is very different in character,
poorly described by economists and the
source of the visible and
important changes in the
economy. The industrial system is a dominant
feature of the Industrial State.
Technology means the
systematic application of scientific or other organised
knowledge to practical tasks. —p31
The application of technology
requires the subdivision of
activity into small enough tasks that they can be analysed using
scientific or engineering knowledge. Nearly all of the consequences of technology
derive from this need to divide tasks, to bring knowledge to
bear on these tasks, and to combine the
finished product. There are six consequences of real importance:
-
It takes far longer to complete any task,
-
There is a large increase in the amount of capital required,
beyond that needed for increased production — increased time
means increased inventory, increased knowledge is required,
more specialised equipment is used at each stage of
manufacture,
-
The process
becomes ever more inflexible, designs must be known long in
advance and not changed,
-
Specialised manpower is required, with deep
knowledge of a tightly limited area (not necessarily
manpower with more aptitude or skill),
-
The need for
organisation increases as a function of specialisation, and
organisation becomes a specialised role in itself,
-
Planning becomes much more important as a
consequence of the
increased investment of time and money, the inflexibility of the commitment, the need for complex
organisation and the
intolerance of the market
for defective products.
These requirements continue to increase as technology advances.
In some instances, it is becoming difficult for corporations to
meet these challenges, especially when timescales are so long,
capital invested in research and development phases so great,
and the tasks being attempted
so complex that it is not known whether solutions can be found,
that projects become extremely risky. One solution to this
problem is for the state to intervene to absorb the major risks.
Technology, under all circumstances, leads to
planning; in its higher manifestations it may put the problems of planning beyond the reach of the industrial
firm. Technological compulsions, and not ideology or political
will, will require the firm
to seek the help and
protection of the state. —p38
Until the end of the Second World War 'planning' was
viewed with some approval. Since then, the
Soviet emphasis on planning has ideologically coloured the word. However, planning is now a
central component of the industrial system.
Under market conditions, there is some degree of price
elasticity of supply. The
market price is sufficient to stimulate production and supply,
or at worst, by offering a premium production and supply can be
encouraged. Within the industrial system this is no longer
realistic. A product that requires three years of research and
development to produce cannot simply be had today by increasing
the price that the consumer is willing to pay. And
so with a firm's inputs — it is not always possible to go to the market and obtain highly
specialised labour and arcane materials in order to meet a
demand that was not anticipated. Instead, in order for such
production to exist at all, long-term planning is necessary.
Unfortunately, alongside the
existence of long-term planning, a functioning market system is
a danger to those involved. A capricious market may make the fruits of an expensive research
and development effort worthless. Thus, when supplying a product
which is so technologically advanced as to make planning
inevitable, it is perfectly rational for the firms involved to seek to
stabilise the quantity which
will be bought and the
product's price in order to reduce their own risks. There are
three ways of doing this:
-
The market
can be superseded. This can be achieved by vertical
integration. This is especially common when an industry
centrally relies on a raw material, such as petrol on oil,
steel on iron ore, aluminium on bauxite, etc. For an oil
company to acquire a drilling operation greatly reduces its
dependence on the market
price of its input.
-
The market
can be controlled by buyers or sellers. This is done in the case of oligopolistic
markets. A sufficiently large company can set prices without
considering the views of
its suppliers or customers. Its suppliers can be replaced
with in-house supply if necessary, consumers can be softened
up with advertising, in the
knowledge that none are powerful enough to demand a
reduction in price.
-
The market
can be superseded for definite periods by specific
contracts. It is in the
interests of large firms to agree contracts by which both
can extend certainty into the
future, choosing by arrangement to ignore the market altogether. The government also makes such
arrangements, for example by fixing agricultural prices — a
case in which firms too small to control market uncertainty
nevertheless require a stable price, and are forced to look
to government for assistance. The
government also does this for large firms where necessary,
in weapons and increasingly in civilian markets such as
transport aircraft, high-speed ground transport and nuclear
energy. In these cases the
state guarantees a price
sufficient to cover costs and pledges compensation under
circumstances of contract cancellation.
There is a clear association between planning and size. The large corporation can cope with
market uncertainty through diversification, can contract out of
uncertainty, can vertically integrate, can control prices and
consumer demand, can enter contracts to reduce uncertainty with
other large firms, whilst the
small firm cannot. Although small firms can appeal to the state
for help, so too can large corporations.
There is still a myth amongst economists that the increasing concentration of
large firms within the economy
is an attempt to seize industrial
power — use monopoly power to increase prices. It is not
recognised that large corporations are the
only unit of organisation capable to manage planning on a scale
appropriate to contemporary high-technology ventures. A world
without large corporations would be a world without
technologically advanced products.
Secondly, “the enemy of the market is not ideology but the engineer.”2)
Advanced technology and specialisation are leading to increased
bureaucratic planning in both the
Western and Soviet worlds. This is not the
result of ideology, but is made necessary by the requirements of the technology we are coming to take
for granted.
It is a feature of all planning that, unlike the market, it incorporates within
itself no mechanism by which demand is accommodated to supply
and vice versa. This must be deliberately accomplished by
human agency. Such is true of the
supply of savings for capital formation. —p52
A surviving economic myth holds that individual workers make the decision to spend or save their
earned income, the part that
they save funding industrial
investment. This is not true. In 1969, $38 billion was saved by
individuals, $99 billion by business firms. In 1950, the poorest two thirds of the population did not, as a group,
save at all. More than half private savings were made by those
in the top five per cent. There
might be some considerable contradiction in a system which had
to whip the mass of society
into a consumeristic frenzy and then relied on them to forgo
some part of their consumption for adequate saving. Thus, money
for investment is saved mostly by corporations, the remainder by the very rich. The consequence of this is that
within the industrial system, there is no
longer a market for capital. Corporations, where possible,
retain earnings for investment. They do not borrow or lend at a
market rate — they plan to save the
money they themselves need for future investment. They do this
for the same reason that
corporations always seek to supersede and evade the effects of the market — uncertainty is inimical
to efficient planning. In the
Soviet economies, state
planners decide how much money be reserved for new investment; in America, that
decision is made by corporate managers. The two processes are different in
many respects, but in neither is a market mechanism involved.
Savings are also, in ordinary circumstances, superfluous in
quantity. Whereas in a country such as India, capital formation
is of vital importance to growth, in America a rather different
situation occurs. Here, the
primary problem is ensuring that all of the money saved is invested — where
investment falls below saving, not all of the product of the economy can be sold, demand lags
production and the economy
sinks into recession. The
planner's solution is state
intervention — the government's
budget deficit stands ready to spend any differential between
saving and investment to ensure that aggregate demand rises to the level of production. There are
very important consequences of the
abundance of capital within the
industrial state, which is the subject of the next chapter.
The discussion of the different factors of production
— the basic categories of
inputs from which economic goods are made (land, labour, capital
and entrepreneurship) — is an extremely familiar topic in
economics. It is rather surprising, then, that one aspect of
their interaction is very rarely discussed — that of what gives
one or other factor of production power within the economy.
There have been two broad shifts in power between factors in
history. Prior to the industrial revolution, and during the period in which Smith and
Ricardo were writing, power was unquestionably held by
landowners. Malthus and Ricardo were convinced that labour would
regulate its own abundance such that it would always be
available at more or less a subsistence wage — it was never
conceivable that labour might have any power. Entrepreneurship
was of no use — one might even say that it had not been invented
yet. And capital was of little importance — those who had land
were invariably capable of commanding the
minute capital that was required to work it efficiently, and
capital alone was of little productive use to anybody without
land. The market for land was
informally controlled by a landed class who rarely traded land,
preferring to pass their estates intact to their heirs. In 1800,
the governments of Britain and
America were dominated by the
landed gentry. The modern
meaning of 'democracy' initially indicated a government
controlled by landed men, as the
landless could not vote until later.
This changed in the course of the nineteenth century, in the Anglo-Saxon world at least. The scarcity of land was finally
being broken by the new cultivation of America, Canada,
South Africa and Australia. Moreover, the
industrial sector was growing in
importance — it was becoming possible to create economic
organisation with capital, labour, the
new invention of
entrepreneurship and only the
tiniest amount of land. Anybody with money could buy land. Power
was shifting from land to capital as capital became the economic “factor [that was]
hardest to obtain or replace.”3) By the 1840s, capital was so
represented in the British
parliament that the Corn Laws
were repealed, confiscating a guaranteed income to landowners
and lowering industrial
(subsistence) wages by driving down the
cost of living. By 1900, the
British and American governments were dominated by
industrialists and businessmen.
The second shift in power has
been occurring over last fifty years (to 1970) and is not yet
finished. Nevertheless it has not yet been recognised. This is
not particularly surprising, as the
reign of capital, just like the
reign of land before it, is seen as eternal. Ricardo believed
that the process of improving
technology would increase the
rent of land indefinitely, that all other factors would remain
in the same miserable condition
forever. However, corporations are no longer influenced by their
stockholders, they are able to find funds sufficient from their
needs in retained earnings. The
following are symptoms:
the loss of
power by stockholders in the
modern corporation, the
impregnable position of the
successful corporate management, the
dwindling social magnetism of the
banker, the air of quaintness
that attaches itself to the
suggestion that the United
States is run by Wall Street, the
increasingly energetic search for industrial
talent, the new prestige of education and
educators… —p73
In the industrial state,
the scarcest factor of
production is “the association
of men of diverse technical knowledge, experience or other
talent which modern industrial
technology and planning require.”4) This
is not the same as labour.
Labour has won some power over its pay and working conditions
but none over the enterprise,
and it still tends to be in abundance. When insufficient savings
are invested and aggregate demand dips below production,
unemployment is the result.
When savings are used, one consequence is automation and the replacement of workers with no
or standard skills with machines. Thus labour and capital suffer
from the new abundance of capital. Nor is
this new factor the same thing as entrepreneurship,
which is of little and diminishing value within the industrial
system. It is a genuinely new
factor of production, and it already holds unrivalled power
within the industrial society.
Individualism is still highly glorified within our culture, but
within the industrial system, the decisive unit of decision-making
is the group, specifically the committee. There are three main
reasons for this.
Firstly, the technology
involved in corporate decision-making requires information to be
provided and interpreted by specialists in various different
fields merely for a single decision to be made. Although in
almost all cases it would be possible for an exceptionally
capable individual to gain simultaneous specialist knowledge in
multiple diverse fields in order to be capable of making such a
decision without relying on further experts, this is an
inefficient use of expertise and talent, the scarcest resource in modern
business. Better to assemble a group of separate experts of
ordinary talent. The results
will be more predictable. “The
real accomplishment of science and technology consists in taking
ordinary men, informing them narrowly and deeply and then,
through appropriate organisation, arranging to have their
knowledge combined with that of other specialised but equally
ordinary men.”5)
Secondly, the degree of
planning required to organise even modest tasks within the industrial
system requires an amount of work which cannot be completed by
an individual. The replacement
of the free market with a
planned solution puts action and decision-making beyond the reach of individuals.
Thirdly, coordinating a range of specialised talent is a complex
process in itself. It requires a delicate group dynamic in which
a committee develops the
experience it needs to vet the
information it requires to make decisions. It will learn to take
some sources of information at face value, treat others at an
appropriate discount, and develop mechanisms to probe and test
potentially spurious sources.
Thus, significant decision-making in all large corporations is
undertaken by groups. This has lead to a fundamental change in the form of bureaucratic hierarchy.
The main difference is that it
is no longer realistic for a superior to overrule a group
decision, as it is for a superior to overturn a decision made by
an individual. In the absence
of committee decision-making, it is generally feasible for a
manager to reappraise any decision made by a subordinate, assess
all of the information used to
make that decision personally, and overturn the decision if appropriate. It is
almost never possible for an individual to adequately appraise a
committee decision — otherwise a committee would not have needed
to be formed in the first
place. Only a second committee containing a similar range of
talent and expertise would be in a position to do so, and in
practical terms this is almost never a remote possibility. Thus,
ultimate power in decision-making is now becoming firmly
embedded within groups somewhere in the
middle of the hierarchy of
corporations. Whilst upper management retains the formal power to ratify
decision-making, in truth he cannot competently decide anything,
and indeed interference in committee decision-making can be
dangerous — it can easily undermine the
efficient process of group decision-making. The only power that remains with
those above such committees in the
hierarchy is that of selecting the
men that comprise the
committees, constituting and reconstituting these groups. The Technostructure is suggested as
a collective term for all those involved in group
decision-making and the
organisation which they form.
Dominant trends in the
development of the corporation
have been ignored by economics, although there are great
differences between different types of corporation. It will be
useful to distinguish between the
Entrepreneurial Corporation, in which due to limited planning
requirements it is still feasible for the
corporation to be understood and managed by a single individual,
and the Mature Corporation, in
which effective control has passed decisively and irrevocably to
the technostructure.
The most obvious requirement of
planning is size. This is not properly understood. Economists
have suggested that corporations are large because of technical
economies of scale or because of a desire to use market power to
inflate prices. Both are partial answers. Technology dictates
large size but does not explain wide diversification. Planning
in a sense requires market power, but it is the power to control supply that is
often inadequately provided by the
market, the stabilisation of
demand, provision of capital and the
general minimisation of risk. The
larger the corporation, the easier this planning becomes.
The corporation has come
efficiently to protect the
technostructure by preventing interference in its decisions. The idea of state interference is taboo.
Although the influence of
stockholders is maintained in myth, it is now almost impossible
for stockholders to impose its will on management in even the most extreme cases: stock is too
diversely held, there are various sundry impediments to
stockholders attempts to intervene, and most importantly, the knowledge required to appraise the firm's activities or make useful
judgements about its operations is impossible to obtain, the company's operations being too
complex. The influence of
capitalists is lessened by the
abundance of capital, enabling large firms to obtain finance
without losing any control; it is enhanced by the complexity and opacity of
operations which make it impossible for financiers to understand
enough to add conditions to finance; but it is generally removed
entirely by financing the
majority of new investment with
retained profits. The only
circumstances under which the
autonomy of the technostructure
is threatened is a failure of earnings. The obvious solution being, of
course, that the mature
corporation almost never fails to turn a profit. “From 1954 to
1969, there was only one year in which as many as three of the hundred largest industrial corporations lost money.”6)
Typically, there comes a point in the
development of a corporation in which the
operation becomes too technologically advanced and the requirements for planning so
extensive and diverse, that effective control by a single
entrepreneur becomes simply impossible. Typically, power is
peacefully transferred from the
individual who created and agglomerated a large corporation to a
technostructure which maintains it in its maturity. The rare cases in which this
transfer is resisted by the
entrepreneur illustrate the
inevitability of this progression, particularly Henry Ford's
attempts to cling to power in the
late 1930s and 1940s. It is customary for the myth of rugged individual
entrepreneurship to be handed down to the
new generation of managers, but
it is not hard to spot the
absurdity.
Individualism is the
note that 'sounds through the
business creed like the pitch
in a Byzantine choir.' 'They're bred to race. It's the same with people. It's
something that's born into you.' 'Business is tough — it's no
kissing game.' These characteristics are not readily
reconciled with the
requirements of the
technostructure. Not indifference but sensitivity to others,
not individualism but accommodation to organisation, not
competition but intimate and continuing cooperation are the prime requirements for group
action. —p106
Modern executives in mature corporations are highly replaceable
men of modest talent. They are ignored by financial markets
whilst in office (unlike entrepreneurial leadership in smaller
firms) and by everybody else the
moment they leave the company.
The names of Rockefeller,
Morgan, Duke, Harriman, Guggenheim, Durant, du Pont, Chrysler,
Hartford and Hilton are remembered, their successors are not.
In any industrial enterprise,
power rests with the
decision-makers. In enterprises committed to the use of advanced technology and
planning, decision-making and thus power must have passed,
inevitably and irrevocably, to the
technostructure. Outside interference with this decision-making
process will inevitably be arbitrary and therefore almost
invariably damaging.
Thus, the socialist faces a
choice in the administration of
the nationalised firm. Either
autonomy must be largely ceded to the
firm's technostructure, in which case management will be
effective and efficient but not subject to democratic control,
or else tight control can be maintained by ministers, in which
case ignorant interference with poorly understood technical
decisions will make the firm
inefficient and unsuccessful.
In the British post-war
adoption of socialism, the
British parliament, with its “superior instinct for
administration, recognised the
need for autonomy of the
nationalised industries.” This was largely granted, and the results were successful.
Parliamentary questions were not permitted on the decisions of the technostructure.
This autonomy is necessary both for small
decisions and what appear to be large questions of policy.
Whether to rely on atomic energy for power is, assuredly, a
question of policy. But the
comparative advantages of atomic and molecular reactions for the generation of electricity are
decided only by a variety of scientific, technical, economic
and planning judgements. Only a committee, or more precisely a
complex of committees, can combine the
knowledge, training and experience that must be brought to
bear. —p112
Elsewhere, in particular in the
former British and French colonies, socialistic policies were
implemented rather differently, with government maintaining much
tighter control of nationalised firms. The
results have been far less successful. One particular tendency
in India is for parliament to pressure firms for lower prices
and higher wages. Nationalised firms in India and Ceylon almost
invariably operate at a loss and, significantly, are not able to
accumulate earnings to be used in investment — the principle means by which the Indian economy is likely to
grow. The technostructure would
surely make different decisions if allowed greater autonomy.
Democratic socialism in the industrial system is now as
impossible, on technical grounds, as entrepreneurial capitalism.
However there is “more to the
case for the autonomous public
corporation than the modern
socialist now sees. Public ownership increases the amenability of the firm to social goals.”7)
The assumption of profit
maximisation lies at the heart
of orthodox economic theory. Before the
consequences of the increase in
the power of the technostructure can be analysed,
corporate motivations must be examined; before that is possible,
the enduring assumption of
ubiquitous profit maximisation must be challenged.
This assumption comes in two distinct flavours. In the competitive sector, it is
assumed that profit maximisation is ruthlessly imposed by the market — that a lack of
commitment to this goal over all others will make it impossible
for a firm to remain abreast of profit-maximising competition,
forcing the firm out of
business. In sectors in which the
corporation enjoys significant market power, the situation is recognised to be
different. In such situations, it is recognised that the firm has some potential
discretion in selecting its goals — it could, technically,
pursue other objectives and remain in business. Here, the assumption of profit
maximisation is more abstract. It is usually assumed that
although other options exist, they are never exploited — the firm always uses any market
power it can gain in order to drive profits as high it possibly
can.
In fact, many economists are not so dogmatic, and yet the consequences of the qualifications they place on
this theory are not explored. Dorfman, for example:
On balance, the
maximisation hypothesis is not as firmly grounded in the facts of life as a fundamental
scientific hypothesis should be. But substantial and prolonged
divergences from the
behaviour it implies are rare, particularly in industries with
many participants. –Robert Dorfman, 1965, The Price System
It is not uncommon for economists to vaguely concede that the assumption may not apply to the industrial
system, as though that didn't matter.
The first major problem with
profit maximisation concerns the
managerial revolution: that is, the
transfer of control from the
owner of the firm to a
professional entrepreneurial leadership. In this case, there is
a clear paradox in applying the
assumption that economic agents maximise their returns: it would
be rational for senior management to maximise their own returns
in the form of wages, bonuses,
stock options, pensions, rather than the
profits of the firm. In the early development of the corporation, particularly in the 1930s, this problem aroused
substantial concern and there were numerous examples of
successful attempts by management to fleece their employers. One
result was legislation limiting their power to do so, partly by
requiring disclosure of pay and benefits. However, at the time this was portrayed by some
as a fundamental contradiction which would destroy the capitalist system, although such
consequences were never realised. In fact, in the majority of cases such
exploitation of the firm by its
management never occurred, and in most cases the possibility for management to
vote itself further increases in remuneration survived
throughout and still to this day. Such exploitation was simply
not in accord with “the accepted
canons of behaviour.”
If the subsequent shift of
power from an entrepreneurial leadership to a broad
technostructure is also accepted, then the
assumption of profit maximisation suffers even further.
Additionally, the conditions
under which the technostructure
operates — specifically, the
pervasive use of group decision-making, which creates conditions
under which all employees actions, and frequently thoughts, are
widely known and subject to peer review — makes personal
profiteering very much subject to the
prevailing culture, which broadly disapproves of it.
The members of
the technostructure do not get
the profits that they maximise
[under the assumption of
profit maximisation at firm level]. They must eschew personal
profit-making [because they are under the scrutiny of their peers].
Accordingly, if the
traditional commitment to profit-maximisation is to be upheld,
they must be willing to do for others, specifically the stockholders, what they are
forbidden to do for themselves. It is on such grounds that the doctrine of maximisation now
rests. It holds that the will
to make profits is, like sexual intercourse, a fundamental
urge. But it holds that this urge operates not in the first person but the third. It is detached from
self and manifested on behalf of unknown, anonymous and
powerless persons who do not have the
slightest notion of whether their profits are, in fact, being
maximised. In further analogy, one must imagine that a man of
vigorous, lusty and reassuringly heterosexual inclination
eschews the lovely and
available women by whom he is intimately surrounded in order
to maximise the opportunities
of other men whose existence he knows of only by hearsay. Such
are the foundations of the maximisation doctrine when
there is full separation of power from reward. —p129
There is clearly a need for a better understanding of the motivations of the technostructure; this in turn
ought to unlock explanations of corporate behaviour more
generally. In this context, we are examining why an individual
would choose to adopt an organisation's goals over his own — why
he would work on behalf of an organisation. We introduce a
framework in which the
individual's reasons for adopting organisational goals divide
into four main categories:
-
Compulsion: the
stick. Bad consequences if the
individual does not pursue the
organisation's goals,
-
Compensation: the
carrot. The individual
receives money for serving the
organisation's purposes,
-
Identification: the
individual is convinced that the
organisation's goals and/or methods are superior to his own,
that working for the
organisation is a more effective means of achieving his ends
than working alone, and
-
Adaptation: the
individual sees working for the
organisation as an effective means of altering the organisation's goals to more
accurately reflect his own.
The interaction of these goals
is clearly of interest, and some reasonably strong observations
can be made. Compulsion and compensation are usually found
together. The amount of
compensation usually rises as the
level of compulsion falls. There is also a typical relationship
between the balance between
these two and (a) the wealth of
society and (b) the economic
position of the individual
involved. Poor individuals in poor countries typically face
extreme hardship on losing employment. Their pay is
correspondingly small. The
richer the country, the better unemployment compensation
and welfare is provided to lessen the
compulsion to avoid unemployment. The
wealthier the individual, the better the
prospects for finding another job.
There is an interesting association with slavery. In a very poor
society, the difference between
serfdom, wage labour and slavery may be slight. “The choice between hunger and
flogging may be a matter of taste.”8) As an
economy develops, and the
condition of wage labour improves the
motivation of slaves to escape will grow and the costs of associated with
maintaining slaves will increase. Thus there will be a level of
economic development at which the
maintenance of slavery ceases to be economically viable.
Naturally, at this point the
society will congratulate itself on its newfound civilisation:
In the absence
of the Civil War, slavery in
the United States could have
lasted only a few more years…As in other countries, at a
similar stage in their economic development, slavery would
have been given up. The
reform would have been attributed to the
innate humanity of man to man. By 1880 or 1890 at the latest, the more respected philosophers
would have been congratulating the
nation on having accomplished peacefully what men once feared
could only have been done by war. —p145-6
Identification and adaptation usually come together — the more one identifies with an
organisation's goals, the more
concerned he will be to perfect them, and the more one hopes and expects to be
able to correct an organisation's goals, the more he will support them.
Adaptation is, to an extent, a matter of taste. Some agitate for
change more than others. It is also a more likely motivator the more power an individual has.
Identification and adaptation, taken together, are also
associated with the
compulsion-compensation continuum. The
higher is compensation relative to compulsion, the higher will be these two
motivations. For those who face only tiny compulsion and
superfluous compensation such as senior executives or important
members of the technostructure,
identification and adaptation may be the
dominant motivations.
Significant levels of compulsion will almost invariably drive
out any tendency for an individual to be motivated by
identification or adaptation. One who is forced to support an
organisation is unlikely to believe in its goals or hope to
change it from within, although there are partial exceptions. The prisoner will not hope to change
the goals of the prison, but the draftee may come to support the goals of the war he is compelled to fight.
This framework also explains the
nature of labour relations under different conditions. In poor
countries in an organisation employing low-skill workers
compulsion will be high and will alienate the worker from his employer —
identification and adaptation will correspondingly be
negligible. Labour relations will be harsh and angry and the employer will make no effort to
cultivate loyalty. In a richer country, and amongst better paid
workers, everything is more benign. The
element of compulsion is much smaller and it will be more useful
for the employer to cultivate
identification with the firm.
On both sides the
motivational system both allows and rewards more agreeable
behaviour. This mellowing of relations, the result of wealth, will,
however, be attributed to more humane instincts, greater
employer enlightenment, more responsible unions and the spread of industrial statesmanship. —p147
There has historically been an association between the dominant resource and the dominant form of motivation. The epoch in which land dominated
other factors was associated chiefly with compulsion, with
feudalism and slavery. Compulsion lends itself to agricultural
production and the associated
dispersion of workers; it is poorly suited to town and city
environments. At the beginning
of the industrial revolution, it was
cheaper to run a factory on wage labour than it would have been
to use slave labour. The shift
from compulsion to compensation naturally followed from the shift in dominance from land to
capital. But the old reverence
for compulsion died hard, and respect for its superior
efficiency remains. The opinion
is still widely held that Nazi Germany and the Stalinist USSR reaped great
benefits from their ability to force labour by compulsion; in
fact it is difficult to discern any significant difference. The extra labour Germany extracted
from workers brought into Germany from occupied Europe under
degrees of compulsion was matched by Britain's drive to
encourage women and domestic servants into industry. Compulsion
remains in contemporary (1972) America in the form of the military draft. A mercenary army
would likely be at least as effective.
Similarly, with the transition
of power from capital to the
technostructure, the primary
motivational force has shifted from compensation to the combination of identification
and adaptation. Considering that the
reverence for the value of
compulsion has not yet died, the
task of convincing economists that compensation has given way to
new motives within a substantial
part of the economy will not be
easy. Yet, within the
technostructure, this has already happened to a striking and
decisive degree.
The traditional view of the power hierarchy within a
corporation runs something like that depicted in Figure 1.
Figure 1: Traditional view of Corporate Hierarchy
Power is supposed to stem from shareholders through the board of directors. But power no
longer lies with anonymous shareholders or in a board of
directors that is now largely subservient to senior management.
Instead, the bulk of decisions
stem from groups within the
technostructure. We might alternatively depict the corporation as shown in Figure
2. Rather than illustrate the
supposed flow of power, this separates participants by their
level of commitment to and investment in the corporation. There is a clear
association between these and the
varying motivations for involvement with the corporation. On the periphery are shareholders,
whose interests are purely pecuniary and who would generally
move their capital to another corporation instantly if they
supposed that it would earn a better return. The next circle represents
production workers, whose motivation varies by corporation. In
those in which work is monotonous and uninteresting, in which the corporate ethos appears to value
profit above all else, which enjoys little respect within the community and in which layoffs
are common, production workers are likely to be motivated
primarily by compensation. In corporations in which work is more
skilled, varied and interesting, which perhaps have a more
social role in society, which enjoy the
respect of the community and
which have a proven commitment to the
job security of all their staff, it is likely that part of the production worker's motivation
will come from identification with the
firm. It is highly unlikely that he will have any illusion that
he can influence the firm, so
adaptation is an unlikely motivator. However, for those
employees in the central core,
identification and to an increasing extent adaptation are likely
to dominate compensation as motivators.
Figure 2: Suggested diagram of motivational division within the corporation
Professors Simon and March suggest the
following circumstances which induce identification of the individual with his
organisation:9)
-
Primarily, obviously, he believes that the organisation shares his
goals,
-
The prestige
of the organisation is
widely perceived,
-
There is frequent interaction between
individuals comprising the
organisation,
-
Many of the
individual's needs are met by the
organisation, and
-
Competition between members of the organisation is minimised.
“All of these requirements are met in the
large corporation, and increasingly so in the inner circles of the technostructure.”10) The power of adaptation as a
motivating force is greatly enhanced by the human instinct to parochialism —
to perceiving the sub-universe
of the organisation in which
his life exists as the only
realm of any importance in the
world.
It is asserted that there is a general principle of consistency
between the motivations and
goals of individuals, of organisations in which they operate and
society as a whole. It is not possible for these goals to be
greatly at odds with one another, because of the process by which they interact.
At present the dominant
organisational system is the industrial system and the dominant individuals within it
are the technostructure. Thus,
to a large extent, corporate goals are consistent with (and
guided by) individuals' goals, and social goals are consistent
with (and guided by) the goals
its largest corporations. This is, to an extent, a two-way
process — society does impose goals on corporations and thereby
on individuals, but the extent
to which social goals are formed by the
technostructure via corporations is substantial. The individual is particularly
motivated to work for a corporation which is perceived to
faithfully serve society's goals. This remains true even if
society's goals have been shaped by corporations to align with the private goals of the individual member of the technostructure.
For both individuals and corporations, pecuniary interest will
be a strong motivator beyond a sufficient threshold. Above that
threshold, it will be less important than other motivations. The technostructure, in its
day-to-day involvement with the
tasks of producing goods and managing demand for those goods,
believes strongly in these goals. Thus, society values
production as an article of faith, even if this production has
negative consequences:
From a detached point of view, expansion in the output of many goods is not
easily accorded a social purpose. More cigarettes cause more
cancer. More alcohol causes more cirrhosis. More automobiles
cause more accidents, maiming and death; also more pre-emption
of space for highways and parking; also more pollution of the air and the countryside. What is called a
high standard of living consists, in considerable measure, in
arrangements for avoiding muscular energy, increasing sensual
pleasure and enhancing caloric intake above any nutritional
requirement. Nonetheless, the
belief that increased production is a worthy social goal is
very nearly absolute. —p172-3
Successful planning in high technology areas requires state intervention — this too is
viewed as a laudable social goal, especially if the goods so produced have a
military function.
This process is highly successful in our time.
Much of what is believed to be socially important is, in fact,
the adaptation of social
attitudes to the goal system
of the technostructure. What
counts here is what is believed. These social goals, though in
fact derived from the goals
of the technostructure, are
believed to have original social purpose. Accordingly, members
of the corporation in
general, and of the
technostructure in particular, are able to identify themselves
with the corporation on the assumption that it is serving
social goals when, in fact, it is serving their own. Even the most acute social conscience
is no inconvenience if it originates in one's own conscience
and is identical therewith. —p172
To reiterate, the conventional
wisdom has a narrow conception of the
goal of economic agents: maximisation of personal pecuniary
return (unless they happen to be working for a corporation, in
which case they will naturally maximise the pecuniary return of an anonymous
shareholder). This is also politically reassuring, placing the consumer — the public — in the position of preeminent power
within the production system. The consumer is sovereign, the producer is a servant. Within
such a framework, the idea that
corporations pursue their own goals or shape those of society is
more or less unthinkable.
If [the reader]
suspects that economics, as it is conventionally taught, is in
part a system of belief designed less to reveal the truth than to reassure
students and other communicants as to the benign tendency of established
social relations, he will…be right.
For it is so. Modern economic belief is the servant, in substantial
measure, of the society which
nurtures it. And not the
least of its services to that society is to render instruction
to the young which, rather
systematically, excludes speculation on the way the
large economic organisations shape social attitudes to their
ends. Nor is the service less
important for being rendered, in the
main, in innocence and in the
name of scientific truth. On the
contrary, were it arranged and paid for, it would cease to be
of much effect. The wiles of
the prostitute can be far more
professional and superficially compelling than those of her
artless competition, but many more men succumb to the latter. —p175
Now the goals of the technostructure, and therefore the industrial
system can be enumerated in more concrete fashion:
-
The
preeminent goal of any organisation or organism is survival.
Corporate survival relies on a secure minimum of earnings.
If this requirement is not met, the
corporation's autonomy is vulnerable to two threats:
-
Interference from stockholders —
struggles for control of corporations are observed only
when suffering losses or meagre earnings, and
-
In the
absence of insufficient retained profits, the need to appeal to
outside sources of investment capital invites
disagreeable scrutiny of the
technostructure's activities.
-
The
secondary goal of
the
technostructure is growth, measured in sales volumes. This,
two, is an act of self-preservation on
the part of
the technostructure. A
contraction in sales volumes in
the
mature corporation threatens
the
secure tenure of members of
the
technostructure. Even those not immediately vulnerable to
unemployment will be far more averse to seeing members of
the technostructure made
unemployed than they would be of blue collar workers.
Decisions to make people redundant must be made within
the technostructure itself, and
“do not have
the agreeable
impersonality which is associated with firing someone at a
greater distance, or of a different social class.”
11)
The main defence mechanism
against contraction is a modest expansion — thus sales
growth represents a solid survival strategy for members of
the technostructure. Moreover,
growth represents a key means of maximising pecuniary return
for members of
the
technostructure. An expansion of
the
technostructure within
the
corporation provides more opportunities for promotion and
usually greater remuneration, and those employees
responsible for
the growth
are likely to be
the
favoured candidates. Sales growth, far more than dividend
growth, is in
the personal
financial interest of
the
technostructure.
-
No further goals can be allowed to interfere
with the first two, but if
both of the first two goals
are met, then further aims are possible. The third is likely to be
technical virtuosity. This is often appreciated by members
of the technostructure in
its own right. It also reinforces the
position of the
technostructure — the
technostructure came to power on the
back of technological complexity, and ever-expanding
technological complexity assures the
corporation's ever-increasing dependence on the technostructure. However,
serious research and development is often risky, and a goal
such as technical virtuosity cannot possibly be allowed to
conflict with the primary
goal of securing a minimum income. Consequently, the cost and risk of
technological development is passed off to the state.
-
Of similar importance to (3), and with a
conscious concession to economic orthodoxy, an increase in
the rate of dividends is clearly
amongst
the corporation's
goals. However, it is clear that this goal must not be
allowed to interfere with (2). “Nothing better suggests
the primacy of growth to profit
than
the vehemence with
which
the sacrifice of
growth to profit would be condemned as unsound business
practice.”
12)
-
If all of the
above four can be achieved, then there will be space for the corporation to pursue any
number of more whimsical goals to which it may be attracted:
Building a better community; improved
education; better understanding of the
free enterprise system; an effective attack on heart ailments,
emphysema, alcoholism, hard chancre or other crippling
disease; participation in the
political party of choice; and renewed emphasis on regular
religious observances are all examples of such further goals…
Nearly all economists, and a great many others,
dismiss pursuit of such goals as irrelevant window-dressing.
This is an error. So long as their subordinate role is clearly
recognised, including the
limitations imposed by cost, they are a perfectly plausible
expression of the goals of the individual members of the technostructure and, thus,
collectively of the mature
corporation. What has been called the
'social corporation' is a logical manifestation of the mature corporation and the motivation of its members.
—p184
These goals of the
technostructure, and in turn of the
corporation, are usually reflected in the
values of society. The
principle of the autonomy of the corporation is perhaps as great
as any.
The grounds on
which this autonomy is defended are palpably bogus. It is held
that nothing must interfere with the
independent operation of the
market mechanism to which the
firm is subject. The reality
of the case of the mature corporation, as we have
sufficiently seen, is that prices are substantially controlled
by the firm and the latter goes on to exercise
influence on the amounts that
are purchased and sold at these prices. —p178
The growth of the corporation is in accord with the central importance of growth in
GNP to society, which is agreed without question to be the primary goal of society
throughout the world, including
the Soviet world and the ancient civilisations of China,
India and Persia, although this is partly due to anachronistic
reverence for increased production. Technical progress is
similarly coveted: “One would encounter less dispute, on the whole, by questioning the sanctity of the family or religion than the absolute merit of technical
progress.”13)
Luckily, this predisposes the state to generously support the more risky and expensive areas
of research and development that would threaten the firm's survival if attempted in
the private sector.
Profitability, and offering an increasing return to the shareholder is similarly held in
high esteem by society. The
member of the technostructure
can therefore feel fuzzy in the
knowledge that his service to his corporation ultimately serves
the highest aims of society,
remaining conveniently less aware of the
extent to which these aims are shaped, in turn, by the personal needs of the technostructure.
There is a stark contradiction between the
standard analysis of the
dominant market structure of the
industrial system and the reality, both in terms of its
treatment by public policy and its achievements.
Economic orthodoxy has long viewed monopoly as an evil.
Monopolies overcharge and underproduce. In so doing they rob the consumer and distort the proper allocation of resources
by sending away capital and labour which could more effectively
be used in raising their output. Economic theory, in turn, views
oligopoly as little more than an imperfect form of monopoly, in
which each of its ills is present in somewhat diluted form.
Prices are still excessive, output is still restrained —
although there are additional inefficiencies. Prices under
oligopoly are also artificially stable, firms are unwilling to
raise prices for fear that the
other dominant firms won't follow suit and unwilling to lower
prices for fear that other firms will follow. Thus prices remain
at a stable level, even when efficiency requires that they be
changed to adapt to changing conditions (costs and preferences).
Moreover, the dangers in using
price competition lead firms to rely more than ever on
'unproductive' forms of competition: the
oligopolist “remodels, repackages and, on occasion, seeks to
improve his product in order to entice customers from his
rivals.”14) In
particular, saturation advertising is typical of oligopoly
markets — a quintessentially unproductive form of competition. A
monopolist would not so waste resources.
Yet oligopoly is the staple
market formation of the industrial system. “Markets for
primary aluminium, copper, rubber, cigarettes, soap and
detergents, whisky, glass, refrigerators, cellulose fibres,
photographic equipment, cans, computers, sugar, [automobiles]
and numerous other items are each dominated by four firms.”15) So
here is the contradiction:
microeconomists denounce oligopoly as inefficient and wasteful;
macroeconomists gush praise for the
industrial system's unstoppable
progress and ever-increasing efficiency. The management of prices is
denounced as an unforgivable attempt to subordinate the market, and yet the technology which is the engine of improvements in
efficiency relies absolutely on that management.
There is an equal contradiction in the
present antitrust law. It forbids combination by merger and
explicit collusion in price-fixing. It permits large firms to
continue to dominate their markets and to increase in size
through investment and growth in sales, and implicit collusion
in price-fixing. A firm may grow to have a fifty per cent share
in its market, but two firms may not combine to form fifteen per
cent. In most cases explicit collusion could not make
price-fixing any more effective or binding. In these markets it
is practised with immunity. In a few, particularly markets for
big-ticket specialised products for which no standard prices
ever exist, it is extremely difficult motivating executives to
collude in order to mitigate the
risks of unpredictable sales levels and prices — in these cases
such collusion is prosecuted. Antitrust law therefore picks at the edges of the problems of market power, whilst
entirely ignoring the total
dominance of the entire industrial system by oligopoly. In
so doing it serves better to maintain the
illusion that the sovereignty
of the market is preserved than
to actually prevent the
accumulation or continuation of market power: “They do not
preserve the market. They
preserve rather the illusion of
the market.”16)
The main contradiction between a
price theory that condemns oligopoly and the consistent efficiency and gains
of an industrial system based
on this structure can be resolved through a better understanding
of the role of prices in industrial planning.
The most basic need of the technostructure — to prevent its
revenue source from falling beneath a lower threshold — requires
the control of prices. This need
is made acute by large and long-term investments in technology —
prices, demand and revenues must be guaranteed into the future in order to protect the firm from heavy losses.
Further, far from fixing prices to serve only the textbook monopoly goal of profit
maximisation, prices will instead by set to serve the goals of the technostructure. These call for
a compromise between competing goals. First of all, prices must
be stable — this is a requirement of successful planning. Were the price for cars determined by
market forces, it would be impossible for large automotive
manufacturers to plan with sufficient accuracy to avoid, on
occasion, disastrous losses. If the
markets for automotive components and labour similarly
capricious, the corporate
planner's task would be impossible. But beyond stability, the general level of prices is
dictated by secondary goals of the
technostructure. Growth in sales requires a low enough price to
encourage increasing demand — but also a high enough price to
guarantee sufficient revenue to cover new
investment in capacity. Prices must also be high enough to
maintain a sufficient return to shareholders, whatever that is
deemed to be by the
corporation. Thus a balance is maintained through compromise
between competing needs. This is the
reason that price control by the
large corporation is associated with efficiency and economic
success — it is a precondition of the
technological deployment and planning that are required for
modern industrial enterprise. The ideology of the market is strong enough to make
it difficult to perceive that the
control of prices by corporations can have a positive effect,
but all successful industrial
states use this corporate price control in some measure — apart
from in Canada and Britain it usually appears in more open form.
Socialist industry also works within a framework of controlled
prices.
When price control is seen to be directed
towards ensuring the security
of the technostructure, as
serving also the goal of
growth and, more than incidentally, also providing a stable
numerator for planning decisions, there is no longer anything
startling in its de facto exemption from the antitrust laws…
The mature corporation has
taken control of the market —
not alone the price, but also
what is purchased — to serve not the
goal of monopoly but the
goals of its planning. Controlled prices are necessary for
this planning. And the
planning, itself, is inherent in the
industrial system. —p201-202
The industrial
system relies on its control of prices in the markets in which it operates to
make long-term planning possible, by guaranteeing an acceptable
level of revenue. But clearly, the
volume of products each corporation is able to sell at its fixed
price is equally important to the
security of this revenue. It would be inconsistent of
corporations to invest effort in securing stable prices and do
nothing to manage consumer demand.
In fact, demand is very actively managed. This function of the firm covers not only advertising
functions — itself accounting for $20 billion17) a
year — but also for many other general functions of management
and production: devising a sales strategy, devising a product or
features of a product around which a sales strategy can be
built, product design, and model change in order to provide
strong selling points.
The purpose of demand management
is to ensure that a sufficient quantity of product is bought at
the controlled price. Not all
advertising is devoted to this end, which is of importance to
avoid overstatement. There are forms of advertising such as
classified adverts whose purpose are merely to inform an
otherwise ignorant consumer of the
existence and price of a product for sale. This does not, of
course, imply that the role of
all advertising is merely to provide information about products.
”[A]s I have noted on earlier occasions, only a gravely retarded
citizen can need to be told that the
American Tobacco Company has cigarettes for sale.”18)
Economic theory associates advertising with oligopoly — here it
is a wasteful zero-sum game in which firms compete with one
another for market share because of their inability to compete
on price. “These large advertising budgets, like heavy
armaments, largely cancel each other out. Not even the oligopolists benefit from them.”19)
This is nonsense. This advertising effort shifts demand to the industry from other industries,
it shifts the overall pattern
of demand such that more goods of this class are demanded than
would otherwise be so. In doing so, it shifts a part of the ultimate decision — the 'sovereignty' — as to what is to
be purchased and therefore produced in the
economy from the consumer to the corporation. It also serves to
stabilise the demand faced by
each individual firm — advertising effort will be redoubled in the firm with stagnating or falling
sales, whilst in the successful
firm efforts to create new
campaigns or redesign their products will be more lax. In this
way, the share of demand
between different firms will be, to some extent at least,
self-rectifying, making planning easier. Again, in order to
avoid overstatement there will be exceptions — occasional
products which the consumer
will not accept not matter how large the
marketing effort. The novelty
of these cases serves to illustrate the
point — this process is imperfect but nevertheless strong and
reasonably reliable and is not disproved by its exceptions.
In recent times, those with lower levels of literacy have joined
the class of individuals with
excess money available to spend on satisfying psychic rather
than physical wants. Thus it has been necessary to extend
advertising methods from print advertisements which were
previously sufficient to manage the
demand of the minority of
society who had a malleable demand to the
remainder of the population —
radio and television advertising has filled this gap. It is now
of great importance. “The industrial system is profoundly
dependent on commercial television and could not exist in its
present form without it.”20)
The management of demand is a
mass phenomenon rather than an individual one, and is relatively
subtle. It is perfectly possible for an individual to contract
out of its influence, and this is often used as proof that it
cannot possibly exist: “I know it is not true of me, and I do
not fancy myself cleverer than the
next man in this regard.”21)
Whilst it is true that some people do not watch television, and
that nobody is forced to watch, the
fact remains that the majority
do.
Much of the conventional wisdom
lives or dies on this point. If demand does not arise
autonomously from consumers' inner desires, but rather is
created through a complex sociological process in which both
consumers and producers have a measure of influence, then the free operation of the industrial
system comes under question. It cannot be defended on the basis that it is serving the 'higher purpose' of society's
true needs. It cannot be protected from government interference
or regulation on the basis that
this will distort the
discipline of the market. And
indirectly the aggregate effect
of advertising is to constantly reaffirm the value of goods, the value of production, the value of the industrial
system and the value of the technostructure — to place
material production at the top
of society's goals.
When viewed not in the
context of absolute virtue but in the
narrower context of industrial
planning, it will be evident that advertising and its related
arts have a large social function. This extends on from the management of demand, the necessary counterpart of the control of prices, to the shaping of attitudes necessary
for the performance and
prestige of the industrial system. For advertising
men it has long been a sore point that economists dismissed
them as so much social waste. They have not quite known how to
answer. Some have doubtless sensed that, in a society where
wants are psychologically grounded, the
instruments of access to the
mind cannot be unimportant. They were right. The functions here identified may
well be less exalted than the
more demanding philosophers of the
advertising industry might wish. But none can doubt their
importance for the industrial system, given always the standards by which that system
measures achievement and success. —p215
In the traditional view, market
conditions (demand) are determined by the
inherent desires of the
consumer; the firm is forced to
respond helplessly to those conditions. The consumer is sovereign, the firm subservient. Let this be
known as the Accepted Sequence.
The accepted sequence persists
in the competitive markets
outside of the industrial system. Within the industrial
system, it provides only a partial explanation. There is a
separate mechanism, by which corporate functionaries create and
distort consumer preferences, as well as market prices, so that
market demand is managed by corporations.22) Let
this latter be known as the
Revised Sequence.
I do not suggest that the
revised sequence has replaced the
accepted sequence…Within the
industrial system the consumer can still reject
persuasion. And, in consequence, through the market he and his fellows can
force accommodation by the
producer. But consumers, and the
prices at which they buy, can also be managed. And they are. The accepted and revised sequences
exist side by side in the
manner of a reversible chemical reaction. —p217
There are enormous consequences of challenging the accepted sequence. The defence of the free market from interference or
regulation is no longer justified by the
higher authority of the
individual's right to buy what he wants — instead only the seller's right to manage the individual remains as a means of
defending corporate autonomy, which seems to lack a some of the rhetorical charm of the former.
The accepted
sequence, with its emphasis on the
assumed power of the
individual, serves in other ways to sanction organisation. Men
accept the disciplines of the great industrial enterprise in order to
serve the ultimate interests
of the individual consumer.
By bowing to rules, subordinating their personality to
organisation, being good members of the
team, they help to enlarge the
range of choice of individual consumers. It is proper that
they subordinate their lesser liberty to that greater one. Or
such is the justification
from conventional economics.
Much more is so justified. Industrial
squalor, air and stream pollution, sacrifice of aesthetic
values — even the rhymed
commercials and billboards which are part of the process of consumer management
— expand the quantity and
variety of product. So they increase the
scope for exercise of the
sovereign power of the
consumer. Again, it is held, lesser values are subordinated to
the greater liberty that is
allied with the ultimate and
controlling power of the
individual in an economic system with a maximum range of
choice. Again economics renders service to industrial purpose.
None of these contentions survives the
revised sequence. There is no case for subordinating the lesser liberty of the organisation man to the greater liberty of the consumer unless that latter
liberty exists. If that has already been subordinated to the organisation, the argument lapses. Industrial squalor serves not the larger liberty of the consumer. It serves industrial convenience. —p221-222
Consumer sovereignty is often explained with analogy to
political democracy — that by casting his ballot in the market-place, the consumer makes the ultimate decision as to what is
produced. The analogy rather
loses its appeal when it is understood that the corporation, through consumer
management, is able to cast a number of the votes — indeed, it begins to
serve better as a condemnation of the
logic of the economic system
than a justification for it.
The problem of regulating
aggregate demand is of much greater scale than the problem of managing demand for
an individual corporation's product — it is of commensurate
significance to the industrial system.
The problem is specific to the industrial
state. In a more primitive state of development, savings are
insufficient and urgently needed. What is saved is invested,
thus Say's law holds — all income is either spent in consumption
or via saving in investment and the
market clears. In the industrial state,
the majority of saving (in 1969
$99 billion compared to $38 billion) is done by corporations,
only a minority by high-income individuals. The relation between retained
earnings and industrial
investment is therefore a planning decision in the hands of the technostructure — there is no
mechanism by which it is stabilised. Indeed, it is frequently the case that a failure in aggregate
demand leads to a more than proportionate reduction in
investment to protect the
technostructure from the
dangers of insufficient revenue. In such circumstances, the system is not self-stabilising
but chaotic — a downward impulse in aggregate demand begins a
spiral. Under Say's mechanism, a failure of aggregate demand
leads to a reduction in prices and the
market clears. In the industrial system prices are a
variable of planning and are not reduced. Instead output and
employment falls.
Aggregate demand can only be managed by the state.
By increasing spending and/or reducing taxation, aggregate
demand can be boosted when it lags, the
opposite operation can reduce aggregate demand when it is
excessive. This requires a large state
sector to make such changes practical. Swings in government
demand are often of the order
of $10 billion in a single year — the
state infrastructure needs to be
far larger than this in order to make such changes practical. In
practice, increases in public expenditure are practical whilst
reductions are not — to be politically viable spending must be
seen as useful, and useful spending is taken for granted as soon
as it is established. Instead taxation is the primary mechanism by which this
is achieved in the post-war
world, through progressive personal income tax and a corporate
tax that, whilst not progressive, acts as such, since corporate
profits are amongst the most
volatile indicators of aggregate demand.
There is a perception that this increase in the role of the state
has been opposed by business. It has largely been opposed by
entrepreneurial businessmen, on whom the
increased tax burden disproportionately falls and who are far
less vulnerable to the failure
of aggregate demand (they are able to respond by laying off
production workers and are not reliant on long-term planning).
It has not been opposed by the
industrial system, who are
highly dependent on it. Business generally opposes social
spending, but never military spending which is understood to be
vitally important to the
technostructure and accounts for between 55 and 60 per cent of
government expenditure in the
1960s. The role of military
spending in assisting the
advance of crucial technology is indispensable — this
expenditure could not simply be replaced by civilian government
or private expenditure.
In much social comment, including that of
numerous economists, there has been a tendency to minimise or
ignore the role of military
expenditures in the
regulation of demand. There is much that is unsettling about
dependence on such outlays. That weaponry in the higher megaton ranges of
destructive power has an organic relation to the performance of the economic system leads to
unpleasant introspection. It seems also a poor advertisement
for the system and lends
comfort to a frequent allegation of Marxists. —p234
There is a firm trend within the
industrial system to reduce the requirement for blue-collar
workers whilst expanding the
technostructure. This is not simply a matter of cost
minimisation, although that is a component in some cases. The technostructure also values
technical virtuosity for its own sake when circumstances allow,
and the continual growth of the technostructure protects them
from unemployment and increases their importance within the firm and within society. It is
natural for those who have decision-making power to approach
problems with solutions borne of their own specialisations and
talents — a highly educated engineer seeks a solution involving
complex and ingenious top-down automated processes, rather than
improvements in working practice that might occur to the assembly-line operative, were he
responsible for improving production. There are also important
implications for planning. A large blue-collar labour force,
especially when under the
influence of a powerful union, is an unpredictable factor of
production. The planner's
ability to deal with the
uncertainty of capricious labour relations is limited. It is
therefore attractive to reduce the
power of unions and the
influence of labour by replacing unpredictable workers with
highly predictable automated processes — even if automation is
more expensive, the elimination
of risk is worth the extra
cost.
It is important to distinguish here between education and skill.
Skilled and unskilled blue-collar workers alike are becoming
redundant; the technostructure
is composed of highly educated individuals. For those in the educational elite, skills may be
reacquired relatively easily — with a college education
retraining for a new job is
comparatively easy. But even the
most skilled blue-collar worker is in a very poor position to
retrain for a different function. Formal education is flexible
as a base for any of a number of roles in the technostructure — the skills of the uneducated are often vulnerable
to technological advance.
The nature of unemployment in the industrial
state has changed. No longer is
it attributable to a failure of aggregate demand and no longer
are the unemployed composed of
those willing and able to work if work were available. There is
now a structural component of unemployment — jobs are available
that require highly educated personnel, whilst the unemployed consist primarily of
those who have not completed high school. Superposed on this, a
cycle of unemployment related to aggregate demand persists, but
it is no longer the only
feature. One consequence is that simple unemployment statistics
are no longer sufficient to describe the
important features of current unemployment.
The requirements of the economic system of the educational system have changed,
and there is a lag in the
response. An increase in investment in education and changes
which encourage a greater quantity to complete higher levels of
education is resisted. Partly it is resisted by business outside
of the industrial system, whose need for
highly educated personnel has not significantly changed, and who
will nevertheless be forced to pay for the
increased government expenditure. Partly it is in the nature of social response that
there is a lag whilst culture and attitudes adjust. Unemployment
in Western Europe has been significantly lower than in the US partly because aggregate demand has
remained higher, partly because the
industrial system is of less
importance, but also because this adaptation of the education system has been
swifter and more effective. Countries such as Germany, France
and Switzerland have been successfully importing unskilled
migrant workers, so successful has their ability been to educate
their own populations for higher-skilled positions.
This rise in the importance of
education is so important that it is possible to say that it has
changed the nature of class
conflict in the United States.
The significant division is now
no longer between the affluent
and the poor but between the educated and the uneducated.
In recent times education has become the difference that divides. All
who have educational advantage, as with the moneyed of an earlier day, are
reminded of their noblesse oblige and also of the advantage of reticence. They
should help those who are less fortunate; they must avoid
reflecting aloud on their advantage in knowledge. But this
doesn't serve to paper over the
conflict. It is visible in almost every community…
Politics also reflects the new division. In the United States suspicion or
resentment is no longer directed to the
capitalists or the merely
rich. It is the intellectuals
— the effete snobs — who are
eyed with misgiving and alarm. This should surprise no one.
Nor should it be a matter for surprise when semi-literate
millionaires turn up leading or financing the ignorant in struggle against the intellectually privileged and
content. This reflects the
relevant class distinctions in our time. —p248-9
There are two influential conceptual bases for the mechanism by which persistent
inflation becomes established. The
only important one for the industrial system, and therefore the most important one for the industrial
state, is 'cost-push inflation',
or the 'wage-price spiral'.
When the economy is near full
employment and aggregate demand is strong, trade unions find
themselves in a strong bargaining position. There are likely to
be a few unfilled positions amongst blue-collar positions.
Recruitment is difficult. In the
event of a strike, the
workforce cannot be replaced en masse. The
unions therefore press for wage increases. The technostructure fear the unpredictable consequences of a
strike. They recognise that wage increases will make recruitment
for unfilled positions easier, and improve employee retention.
Further, the corporation is not
profit maximising, and the
technostructure knows that it can pass on increased wage costs
to its customers through higher prices. Union arrangements are
usually to some extent industry-wide, so all firms are likely to
accept similar rises in wages. Prices will rise uniformly across
the industry and no firm will
lose out. “And, finally, the
technostructure with which the
decision resides, does not itself have to pay.”23) So,
when aggregate demand is adequate, the
technostructure will readily accept wage demands, passing on
costs to consumers. The price
index rises as a result, leading to a further round of wage
claims in the course of time.
Inflation persists.
Outside of the industrial system the situation is different: here the concept of 'demand-pull
inflation' is more appropriate. The
entrepreneurial firm already maximises profits — wage demands
cannot be passed on to the
consumer and must be paid for out of the
entrepreneur's earnings: “Again there is the special poignancy in paying when
the individual has himself to
pay.”24)
Wage claims will be fiercely resisted. Prices will only rise
when aggregate demand outstrips the
industry's ability to supply, when profit maximisation leads the entrepreneur to increase prices.
This will not happen until aggregate demand is excessive rather
than sufficient, although the
definition of these points is somewhat hazy.
The point is that the wage-price spiral begins before
the economy reaches capacity —
it can only be avoided by reducing demand so much that an
unacceptable level of unemployment results. Persistent inflation
and significant unemployment are both unacceptable. The only solution to this problem is
state control of wages and
prices within the industrial system. This has been
highly effective whenever it has been tried — in the US to a greater or lesser extent since
the Second World War (rigid
controls from 1941 through to the
end of the war, then again
during Korea, followed by informal but significant pressure
under Kennedy and a sudden and rather embarrassing return to
formal controls previously denounced as little short of
un-American under Nixon25)) —
but has somehow never convinced economists of its effectiveness.
For economists, as will be sufficiently
evident, a massive intellectual vested interest was involved.
As noted, nearly all teaching and technical discourse assumed
markets in which producers sought to maximise their return. To
admit of the need for price
or wage control was to admit of the
inadequacy of this system and the
associated theoretical apparatus…Instead of revealing to
students by precise and rational diagrams the prices that would maximise
profits for a producer, it would be necessary to consider what
price a bureaucrat might believe consistent with wage and
price stability. Economist would be reduced to the level of political science.
Truth has its obligations to dignity. —p254
Wage and price controls are traditionally opposed by the entrepreneurial firm and unions.
For the entrepreneurial firm, the only purpose of price and wage
controls could be to reduce profits — resistance is rational.
Within the context of the entrepreneurial firm, unions
feared that wage controls meant wage restraint at the behest of the bosses:
[The
entrepreneurial firm] had a strong interest in resisting union
demands. It had privileged access to newspapers, public
opinion and the state. Any wage regulation, other
than that establishing minimum wages, would be, it was felt,
for the purpose of keeping
wages down. —p254
However, there is no serious reason why those in the industrial
system — both the
technostructure and the unions
— should resist wage and price control. In principle, the government would ensure that
corporations kept prices within the
industrial system remained
stable, and in return the
unions would agree to press for wage increases no larger than the trend rate of productivity
increases within their firm or industry. For the technostructure, this makes
planning easier by reducing uncertainty (albeit an uncertainty
that is relatively easy to deal with). For unions, this removes
the need for a sustained
organising effort merely in order to win gains sufficient to
keep real wages constant.
With minimum prices established by the firms, demand that is managed
by them for specific products, demand that is managed in the aggregate by the state
and maximum levels established by the
state for wages and prices, the planning structure of the industrial
system is effectively complete. All that remains is to ensure
that everyone, at all times, refers to it as an unplanned or
market system. —p261
Outside the industrial system wage and price
controls are not wanted or needed. This sector is not
responsible for the wage-price
spiral and will only lead to inflation if aggregate demand
extends beyond the economy's
capacity. Since controls in the
industrial system are
effectively supported by everyone in the
industrial system, the power which the state
needs to implement them are not particularly large. They have
enjoyed success in the past
with inadequate infrastructure or even through informal
arrangements such as those introduced by Kennedy.
The union is of much less
importance in the industrial system than it is in the context of the entrepreneurial firm. Most of the broad changes that have lead to
the importance of the industrial
system have also contributed to the
loss of power and influence of the
union:
-
The shift in
power from the entrepreneur
to the technostructure, as
previously mentioned, means that those deciding whether to
accept wage demands are no longer those who will pay the bill. The urgency of undermining or
destroying the union felt
by the entrepreneur is not
felt by the technostructure
— the union poses a threat
to planning through the
risk of striking rather than a threat to pecuniary reward
through seizing their profits. Thus it is in the interests of the technostructure to pursue
more docile relations and assent to more generous wage
agreements. Moreover, increased costs can be passed on to
consumers, especially when wage agreements are
industry-wide, signalling equal price increases for all
firms simultaneously.
-
Technological advance reduces
the number of workers within
reach of
the union,
shifting employees in large number into white collar
positions who tend to identify more with management than
with unions.
26)
-
The
regulation of markets and aggregate demand as well as
comparative affluence have reduced
the
dependence of
the worker on
the union. Where previously
the worker had been unable
to find another job because of high level of unemployment,
management of aggregate demand has made this much easier.
Consequently, where
the
union was previously
the
only mechanism by which he could solicit for better working
conditions, and
the only
organisation that could protect him from
the extreme privation of
unemployment, now he is less dependent. He is much more able
to find another job if he is dissatisfied and thus
the problem of recruitment
motivates firms to voluntarily improve conditions.
27)
-
The
imperatives of price and wage regulation place wage
negotiation firmly within the
remit of the state, and are ultimately likely
to demand that wage increases progress in line with industry
average improvements in productivity.
Although the original role of the union is waning in the industrial
system and the numbers of
unionised employees is clearly in decline, new and useful roles for the union have emerged in this
context. In some ways, unions in the
industrial system are becoming
more similar to those in the
Soviet system — in which unions must be allowed to persist as a
symbol of worker power but cannot be allowed to interfere with
workers' identification with the
goals of the firm. The union has emerged as an
infrastructure through which grievances about the fairness of an increasingly
complex pay structure are aired and settled. In some cases
unions have supported the
adoption of new technology, and
have constructively negotiated settlements for reducing
employment as part of these adjustments. They now provide a
convenient voice to proclaim the
needs of the technostructure:
whereas it is uncomfortable for the
technostructure to demand increased defence spending for its own
enrichment and security, it is more acceptable for unions to
advocate such spending to protect jobs and the wellbeing of the community in which most workers
are employed. “On support for the
Vietnam war and on spending for highly technical weapons some
union leaders, in recent years, have been far less inhibited
than management.”28)
Finally, the union is capable
of delivering industry-wide wage agreements, and is a viable
mechanism by which its members can be induced to accept such
agreements — in other words, by which wages can be reliably
controlled. This reduces the
threat of one firm within an industry managing to reduce wages
beneath those of its competitors and thereby underselling the industry. It also makes the state's
problem of agreeing wage controls to prevent inflation far more
manageable.
29)
The educational estate has grown
fortyfold over the past 80
years.30)
This growth has responded to the
importance of trained talent as the
most scarce vital resource in the
industrial society.
Prior to the significance of the industrial
system, the educational
establishment was largely under the
influence of the entrepreneur.
Much of the money which
sustained the few schools and
colleges that existed came directly from rich benefactors, who
believed in “the doctrine of
financial paramountcy — of the
ultimate power of those who paid the
bills”, although this was never fully accepted in the academic community. Indeed, a
significant tension always existed between the private sector who felt
financial measures the
uncontroversial measure of success and academics who, failing
dismally by such measures, tried to assert goals that were
“intellectually more demanding or aesthetically more refined”.31)
This tension was complicated by academia's tendency to be the dominant source of social
innovation — a realm in which corporations have always been
notably sterile. Whilst inconvenient views were often
voluntarily muted or suppressed, nevertheless legislation and
policy antithetical to the
entrepreneurial enterprise originated in the universities:
Laws against monopoly, regulating access to the capital markets, n support of
a wide range of welfare measures, in support of progressive
taxation and on behalf of unions, owed much to such origins.
—p288
During these years the academic
community has been regarded as having been bullied and dominated
by business. Much of this view reflects the fact that the history has been written by
academia. Moreover, the
influence of money is usually rather brutal and unsubtle.
Proposals for reform, by contrast, begin as
seemingly eccentric and implausible suggestions. Gradually
they gain adherents; in time they emerge as grave needs; and
then they become fundamental human rights. It is not so easy
to attribute power to those who set this process in motion.
—p288
The needs of the technostructure and the modern educational estate are
much more closely aligned. The
technostructure is dependent on the
educational estate not only for a constant supply of talent, but
for information about current technological innovation. There
are more acute risks associated with direct criticism of
academics. Moreover, academic ideas are not as threatening to the technostructure as they were to
the entrepreneur. The costs of “improvements in
medical care, guaranteed incomes for the
poor, protection or salvaging of the
environment, regeneration of slums” can be passed on to either
consumers or shareholders, and the
burden of coping with regulation can be passed on to
professional lawyers, accountants and industrial
relations specialists where once these burdens fell squarely on
the entrepreneur. “The burden of regulation like that
of taxation is appreciably lessened by having it fall on someone
else.”32)
Some recent developments that have come from academia have
proved invaluable to the needs
of the technostructure —
particularly the regulation of
aggregate demand and the more
nascent attempts to control prices and wages.33)
The question remains to what
extent the educational estate
has reconciled its goals to those of the
industrial system. There is no
single answer as the
educational estate is importantly heterogeneous, but there is a
trend for the degree of
reconciliation to vary across subjects. ”[E]conomics, as a
discipline, has extensively and rather subtly accommodated
itself to the needs of the industrial
system.”34) So,
to a significant but lesser extent, have the hard sciences and engineering —
who often work closely with the
technostructure and often receives money from them. Much less so
the classics, humanities and
some social sciences and a natural tension has grown up between
the two cultures.
Despite this reconciliation, there remain three main points of
conflict between the
educational estate and technostructure:
The market for
soap can only be managed if the
attention of consumers is captured for what, otherwise, is a
rather incidental artefact. Accordingly, the smell of soap, the texture of its suds, the whiteness of textiles treated
thereby and the resulting
esteem and prestige in the
neighbourhood are held to be of highest moment. Housewives are
imagined to discuss such matters with an intensity otherwise
reserved for unwanted pregnancy and nuclear war. Similarly
with cigarettes, laxatives, painkillers, beer, automobiles,
dentifrices, packaged foods and all other significant consumer
products. —p293-4
The
educational and scientific estate views the effort with distain, even
though, as the
technostructure responds, these efforts are necessary for the effective management of the economic system.
Thus the paradox. The economy for its success
requires organised public bamboozlement. At the same time it nurtures a
growing class which feels itself superior to such
bamboozlement and deplores it as intellectually corrupt. The subculture which requires such
obfuscation for its existence can only be regarded with
disdain. That culture responds with a sense of hurt and guilt
and the indignation which
comes from the knowledge that
its needs sustain and nourish its academic critics. —p294
-
The
educational estate retains a highly individualistic ethic,
and encourages individualistic development in those it
trains. In contrast, they find themselves in a world in
which they, as citizens, consumers, soldiers and
organisational men are expected to be subordinate to the needs of organisation and
planning.
-
There is further conflict in
the developing relations with
the state.
Members of
the educational
estate are in a privileged position in that their
involvement in political matters is less inhibited by
decency. They are also growing rapidly in numbers.
The idea that
the academic community was
becoming a decisive instrument of political power was firmly
denounced in criticism of
the
first edition of
NIS, but since its influence in
retiring Johnson and changing policy in Vietnam, this
suggestion has not seemed so radical.
The relationship between the entrepreneurial firm and the state,
like all relationships of the
entrepreneurial firm, primarily pecuniary and generally
zero-sum. By purchasing influence the
entrepreneur could gain various profitable concessions:
protection from foreign competition, railway and public utility
franchises, licenses to export mineral rights and other natural
resources, exception or mitigation of taxes and armed support
against some of the excesses of
workers' ambitions. Equally, the
entrepreneur had every reason to fear state
power, particularly in the form
of taxation and regulation. Entrepreneurial influence over
government was direct, pecuniary and very great — to the extent that business was
perceived to have bought government. Influence came in the form of purchased votes and
legislators. Large corporations dominated the states in which they were based:
“California of the Southern
Pacific, Montana of Anaconda, Pennsylvania or the steel and coal companies,
Michigan of the automobile
companies”.35)
During the 1930s, there was a
wide perception that this relationship — of business dominating
the state
— was being reversed. It was largely blamed on the unions who, with the support of the intellectual elite, were
enlarging the power of the state
by encouraging it to adopt roles in the
management of aggregate demand and greater support for working
people. In fact the enlargement
of the state that was occurring very much
met the needs of the emerging industrial system.
The relationship between the state
and the industrial system is far from
antagonistic. As already discussed, the
state meets the industrial
system's need for educated talent, stable aggregate demand,
controlled wages and prices and support for the most costly and risky areas of
long-term development of technology. Moreover these policies are
not paid for with money extracted from the
technostructure — as was the
case with the entrepreneur —
but by taxes which can be passed on to the
shareholder and consumer. These policies are of minimal value to
the entrepreneurial firm.
Government has clearly adapted itself extensively to the needs of the industrial
system, and yet the industrial system is much less
capable than the
entrepreneurial class to directly purchase the allegiance of the legislature. Corporations cannot
donate funds directly, but entrepreneurs can pay themselves
dividends and then offer that money as a private donation. Such
arrangements are most easily made between individuals, but the technostructure operates through
group structures. And the
entrepreneur had enough to gain financially to risk being caught
in immoral dealings, whereas salaried technocrats seem less
likely to relish the risk.
Power has passed to the industrial system in a very
different way — in much the
same way that power has passed from upper management into the bowels of the technostructure. In defence, for
example, which accounts for more than half of government
activity, it is barely possible to distinguish between public
and private organisation. The
extent of planning and the
requirements of technology ensure that services and the corporations that supply them
work together in effectively permanent relationships in which
real decision-making emanates from specialist committees as
likely who are as likely to be composed of members of the private sector, and are as
likely to perceive importance in the
goals of the private sector, as
they are to be public servants with purely public interests at
heart. Identification and adaptation dominate the motivational systems of
everybody involved — but those working, strictly speaking, in the private sector identify just as
closely with the public service
they are supplying as they do with their own firm, and vice
versa. The result is that the needs of the corporation are embedded just as
surely in the real
decision-making of defence services as the
needs of the defence service
itself (and in fact, the two
will share many goals: not least the
need to increase the budget and
scale of their operation). The
industrial system comes to
influence government by integrating itself so seamlessly with the outer functions of government
that it becomes artificial to draw a line between the public and private sectors.
Rather than the influence
government decisions, the
technostructure makes government decisions. In defence above
all, decisions made by committees composed of members of the armed services alongside
scientists, engineers and managers from private firms are passed
up to legislative houses that are in no position to adequately
appraise them and are forced merely to ratify.
One consequence of this is that the
industrial system cannot be
concerned with party politics in the
way that entrepreneurs were and still are. The industrial
system is more akin to the
civil service — it must get along seamlessly with whoever is in
power and can rarely afford even to criticise government.
[The
corporation] can help shape the
highly technical choices which, in turn, govern the demand for its own military
and other products. It will have access to the decisions on military strategy
which establish the need for
such products. And it will help to shape the current beliefs or assumptions
on foreign policy. These, obviously, are a far more important
power. It is the difference
between the formal grandeur
of the legislative hearing
and the shirt-sleeved rooms
with blackboards and tables heavy with data, drawings and
tapes where the important
decisions, bit by bit, are actually made. The technostructure selects its
theatre of influence with discrimination and intelligence.
—p316
Poverty remains in the US as in other
industrialised countries, but not within the industrial
system, which has also greatly reduced the
burden of human toil. “Only those who have never experienced
hard and tedious labour, long continued, can be wholly
indifferent to its elimination.”36) The economic system no longer serves
man's “original and sovereign desires” — the industrial
system not only accommodates to men's needs, but also
accommodates men to its needs. This is not peripheral, but a
fundamental requirement of the
industrial system. This control
ensures that men do not work less as more of their wants are
satisfied. Increased production remains the primary goal of society, and
thus the industrial system remains of
paramount importance.
The management
to which we are subject is not onerous. It works not on the body but on the mind. I first wins
acquiescence or belief; action is in response to this mental
conditioning and thus devoid f any sense of compulsion. It is
not that we are required to have a newly configured automobile
or a novel reverse-action laxative; it is because we believe
that we must have them. It is open to anyone who can resist
belief to contract out of this control. But we are no less
managed because we are not physically compelled. On the contrary, though this is
poorly understood, physical compulsion would have a far lower
order of efficiency. —p318
The industrial
system has near total control of its capital supply, significant
control of its labour supply and considerable influence within the state.
State functions necessary to the industrial
system — regulation of aggregate demand, state underwriting of advanced
technology, provision of educated manpower — are considered the highest social goals. Along side
these changes, there has been a dramatic shift in the centre of political and economic
power from the financier and
union to the technostructure,
who exert their influence by very different means — by having
direct decision-making power over the
component planning decisions which ultimately superpose to
determine policy. A large and powerful scientific and
educational estate has been brought into existence to serve the needs of the industrial
system, but remains to some extent independent of it.
There are difficulties in talking, at the same time, about what will
happen and what should happen. Marx must on occasion have
wondered, if revolution were inevitable, as he proclaimed, why
it required the passionate
and unrelenting advocacy which he accorded it. Should baleful
tendencies be predicted when one hopes that popular
understanding will bring the
reaction that reverses them? —p320
Everyone who wins a positive score in an
intelligence test recognises that the
selling of goods — the
management of demand for particular products — requires
well-considered mendacity. —p323
Nobody believes advertisers' claims about ordinary products, yet
this fails to make advertising ineffective. In contrast, the fantasies that are employed in
order to advertise military products to the governmental customer are
believed with fervour, including those purveying these fantasies
although the fantasies are no
less contrivances convenient to the
industrial system. The industrial
system requires a large state
market for high-technology waste and the
customary image which justifies this expenditures has long been
the Cold War. Naturally the origins of the Cold War imagery are real, but
it has been groomed to accommodate the
needs of the industrial system. It is
“relentless, implacable, permanent, but ultimately benign”.37)
Despite similarities in the two
societies' accommodations to the
imperatives of planning, in the
Soviet system the management of
the individual is more direct
and subject to compulsion. The
incompatibility of the two
systems and the evangelism that
accompanies their differences lead to military competition. “All
features of this competition are closely congruent with need.”38) The conflict is permanent, avoiding
the annoying danger in other
forms of warfare for a cessation of hostilities to reduce
military production — “A war without fighting neatly obviates the danger that fighting will stop.”39)
Obsolescence replaces battlefield attrition. Any agreement to
arrest the competition is
universally agreed to be far more dangerous than the competition itself. Without the usual large numbers of the poor fighting and dying, the Cold War is not resisted by the working class as previous wars
have tended to be.
Even a calculation that
the competition may, at some
point, lead to a total destruction of all life is not a
definitive objection. Liberty, not material well-being, is
involved. This is an ultimate value that cannot be compromised
in
the face of any threat. “I
am confident that
the vast
majority of
the American
people would passionately reject…ignominious defeatism and,
instead, proclaim: 'Rather dead than Red!'”
40)
Thus
the competition is
protected from even
the most
adverse estimates of its outcome. —p328
Granting a continuation of or slight increase to the military budget is amongst the easiest decisions a president
can make.41)
It is difficult to believe that implacable conflict is
inevitable between the two
countries. Their economic systems have much in common, indeed the trend is of convergence. The notion that the arms competition is ultimately
benign is similarly suspect. Negotiated disarmament seems
plausible. Agreements are negotiated in good faith with
communists on all other matters.
To eliminate civilised life for all time in
response to a short-run calculation that liberty might
otherwise be endangered is also irrational. And those who
would make such a decision are themselves strongly subordinate
to a particular system of belief. They are not themselves free
men. —p330
In confronting the dangers
involved in the military
competition of the Cold War,
two changes are necessary: firstly to ensure that sceptical
scrutiny of official belief is an important political function
and secondly to replace the industrial system's need for support
in the development of
technology by some less dangerous means. In the past, scrutiny has been a
product of conflict — each party to the
conflict scrutinised its opponent with vigour. The mature corporation has been able
to break down much of this conflict, particularly that between
unions and capital. It does not have as natural an enemy as the entrepreneur. However, the educational estate has been
encouragingly resistant to the
ideas and ideology of the industrial system. “In the last decade there has been a
recurrent conflict between the
university community and the
intellectuals on the one hand
and the State Department and foreign policy
establishment on the
other…this, on the whole, has
been an encouraging development.”42)
With its growing size and power, the
educational and scientific estate now has the opportunity to take on this role
in questioning the imagery and
foreign policy which originates within the
industrial system. “Nothing in
our time is more important.”43)
In the field
of international relations, especially since the onset of the Cold War, high public
officials have invariably been more diligent in instructing
other governments than their own. Though often cautious and
deferential in their relations with the
Congress, Secretaries of State
have been bold and forthright in informing the Soviets of their error. The late John Foster Dulles rarely
missed an opportunity to advise the
Russians on the merits of
liberty and the rule of law
and the sanctity of freedom
of speech. He was much more cautious as regards Senator Joseph
McCarthy although the latter,
on frequent occasions, attacked freedom of expression and due
process and did not omit to concern himself with Mr Dulles'
own Department. Mr Dean Rusk, a circumspect man in dealing
with domestic critics, especially those who might charge undue
liberalism in relations with China, showed contrasting
boldness in telling the
communist powers of their great and varied shortcomings.
Indeed, it may be laid down as a rule of international
relations that the lower the probability that advice will
be taken, the more firmly it
will be proffered. —p333
Mutual disarmament should be lead by the
US. This
is the country in which we have
the influence necessary to enact
this policy. It is also by far the
richer of the two, and
consequently tends to set the
pace of the competition. It
cannot be known whether an agreement for negotiated disarmament
can be reached with the
Soviets. We do not fully understand the
imagery to which Soviet society is subject. But it must be
attempted.
It must be fully recognised that the
traditional economic view that military spending can be replaced
with private-sector or social spending is false, failing to
recognise the important role
military spending plays in underwriting new technology. But non-violent
alternatives exist, the most
obvious contemporary example being space exploration although
any form of expensive, high-technology research and development
project will serve.
Those features of the state which are not of importance to
the industrial
system tend to be neglected and regarded as unimportant. These
fall into two categories:
-
Those services which are unneeded by the industrial
system — these suffer by competing for public funds with
services which are of value to the
industrial system, and
-
Services associated with state goals which are alien or
inimical to the industrial system.
In the former category fall
services such as healthcare, elderly care, provision of parks,
removal of rubbish, provision of decent public buildings and
assistance for the poor. The active management of private
demand inflates the demand for
private goods. The influence of
the industrial
system inflates the
government's perceived need to spend money on those services
which benefit the industrial system. By comparison,
demand for government services which are of no use to the industrial
system is not artificially inflated by any concerted effort.
Such services naturally suffer. This is addressed in greater
detail in the Affluent Society.
The world of “aesthetic
experience” may be contrasted with the
world of production. This world is served not by scientists and
engineers and thus not by the
technostructure, but by artists. Prior to the industrial
revolution, a large part of life was devoted to the aesthetic experience —
unimaginably large, given the
resources of earlier societies and the
extreme bias toward production in the
industrial state. The
truly beautiful cities of the
world: “Athens, Florence, Venice, Seville, Agra, Kyoto and
Samarqand” are all preindustrial — no city built since The Wealth of Nations can possibly
compete, though these cities were infinitely poor by modern
standards.
Aesthetic achievement is beyond the
reach of the industrial system and is therefore
little valued by it. Moreover, aesthetic considerations are
often inconvenient to the industrial system — it would be
distinctly inconvenient if the
aesthetic consequences of positioning a factory had to be
considered equally along side questions of efficiency, if the polluting consequences of
production were to be as readily considered as the financial implications.
Aesthetic considerations are almost never considered in industrial planning — on the few occasions in which they are,
their advocates normally have to present a case illustrating
that following the
aesthetically preferable route will for some reason not be
damaging to the economy in the long term.
Advertising relies on a jarring dissonance — a billboard that
blends subtly into the
landscape is ineffective and this can even more readily be seen
in television advertising.
[A]n effort is made to bring this dissonance
within the ambit of social
goals. It is defended interestingly by the contention that it 'gives the consumer what he wants'. If he
did not approve, he would not respond. A man who comes to a
full stop because he is hit over the
head with an axe proves similarly by his response that it was
what he was yearning for. —p344
Aesthetic achievement relies on individuals. It cannot be
produced by committee.
The aesthetic
dimension being beyond the
ready reach of the industrial system, members of that
system are led naturally to assert its unimportance. Juveniles
who do not like Latin, economists who do not like mathematics
and men who do not like women manifest precisely the same tendency. —p345
Any importance accorded to the
aesthetic dimension automatically grants a greater role to the state
— only the state can protect the rural and urban environment from
ugliness or radio and television from “contrived dissonance”.
And any such promotion of the
aesthetic dimension is bound to come at some cost to GNP.
That one must pause to affirm that beauty is
worth the sacrifice of some
increase in the Gross
National Product shows how effectively our beliefs have been
accommodated to the needs of
the industrial
system. —p345
When urban spaces are managed by democratic governments they are
usually rather ugly. “Although the
world owes more to public architecture than to private, it owes
more to the taste of talented
despots…than to democrats.”44) The only outcome substantially worse
than planning by a democratic authority is that created by no
planning. Politicians generally deem their own tenure a success
if they can leave office knowing that society is richer than
when they arrived. Even the
most incompetent succeed by that measure. A much more severe
test would be whether they leave their country more beautiful
than before.
None in this country would have passed. The fact of universal failure is
another reason for insisting on the
importance of the aesthetic
dimension. No one likes an examination which he surely flunks.
But far more than the test of
production, which is far too easy, the
test of aesthetic achievement is the
one that, one day, the
progressive community will apply. —p348
The myth that the market efficiently regulates our
economy creates many dangers. One is the
tendency for efforts to correct a failing market, when it
happens to fall outside of the
industrial system, to be weak
and half-hearted. If, instead of assuming that by default the market will efficiently allocate
resources it were properly recognised that in some instances the market is successful and in
others planning is more appropriate, then cases in which a
powerful state planning
machinery is required to solve major problems would be much more
easy to recognise. At present there are gaps (lacunae) in what
should rightly be the planned
sector of the economy, with the consequence that the public's needs are poorly met.
There are two particularly clear contemporary examples in the United States.
Firstly, mass urban and inter-urban transportation. This
requires a single overarching corporation with the competence and power to plan a
unified mass transit system of trains, buses and trams. The piecemeal and competing systems
current in the US are simply
very poorly suited to a market which would benefit enormously
from a single planning unit. Such a unit, if it was large enough
to satisfactorily control its labour needs and retain its own
earnings to meet its capital needs, transferring the cost and risk of major
technological improvement to the
state under the traditional excuse of urgent
defence need, with its own technostructure and active inflation
of consumer demand similar to that by airlines and automobile
manufacturers, would be a far more effective and successful
provider of public transport than we now have. Although the comparison is imperfect, the telecommunications sector is
similar in some ways, and has benefited enormously from
AT&T's monopoly — this sector could not have survived in a
useful form if a similar market structure to that for transport
systems had been imposed on it.
Although less obvious, the
second is more important — the
market for urban and suburban housing. This fails abjectly to
meet human need, and continual interference by government
through subsidies and building regulations have long been
insufficient to make any real difference. The failures are recognised, but
assumed to be isolated failures of the
market. But the only means of
truly solving the problem is to
have a strong planning, housing and development authority which
could buy up land where necessary.
There should be no default assumption that either the free market or a planned
solution is more appropriate for any given industry. This
requires a sharp rejection of the
traditional economic approach, and a revised attitude towards the concept of consumer sovereignty.
If the market prevails, it is
supposed, then the principle of
consumer sovereignty implies that whatever is produced is wanted
— only an elitist hater of democracy could argue that production
priorities ought to be changed. But if the
revised sequence is accepted, then the
observation that too many automobiles are produced and there is
insufficient inter-urban transport infrastructure may just as
easily indicate that the
automobile industry has a greater power to control the preferences of the public.
Consumer sovereignty by making questions about
too many automobiles, too few houses, an elitist and
undemocratic interference with consumer choice, excludes
questions about the power of
the automobile industry to
impose its preference on the
public. This, in effect, is the
result of existing economic theory. It gives high moral and
scientific sanction to social indifference. —p356
Don't mourn for me friends, don't weep for me
never,
For I'm going to do nothing forever and ever. –Traditional
Epitaph of an English Charwoman
One of the great promises of the industrial
system has been the replacement
of work with leisure. In the
early stages of the industrial system, toil was dreary,
repetitive and physically painful. It was also very long. It is
perfectly natural that a labourer working an eight-four hour
week to earn the barest living
will choose to realise any improvement in productivity in
increased leisure rather than income. This is no longer true.
Over the last thirty years,
working hours have remained constant whilst before-tax real
income has doubled.45) “On
the evidence, one must conclude
that, as their incomes rise, men will work longer hours and seek
less leisure.”46)
Although there are exceptions, work within the industrial
system is no longer as painful or boring as that which preceded
it, and it can no longer be assumed that work is less pleasant
than not working — “Presiding over the
console that regulates the
movements of billets through a steel mill may be as pleasant as
sojourning with a connubial fishwife.”47) If
leisure is to be voluntarily chosen over work, then two
prerequisites must be satisfied:
-
They must find the
uses of leisure more interesting or rewarding than those of
work, and
-
They must have sufficient independence from the management of their wants to
be capable of making a choice contrary to the wishes of the industrial
system.
Education seems to be the most
plausible way of meeting these prerequisites: those most closely
associated with academia conform readily to the stereotype of the man whose demands are not
managed by advertising and who actively manages his free time
creatively:
Excessive attention to goods is considered
gauche; an elderly automobile or a Volkswagen, casual and
shabby clothing, undistinguished by ostentatiously comfortable
furniture, self-designed entertainment, unluxurious travel, the absence of a television
receiver, and functionally clothed women are sources of
distinction [for the typical
academic]. —p359
Most people will consider that the
greatest possible emancipation of the
individual from the management
of the industrial system will be a worthy
goal, even at considerable cost to the
industrial system by its own
standards. The opportunity for
such emancipation lies in education.
It would also be of great benefit if the
individual worker were able to mould the
working week and year to his personal needs, permitting those
who wish for a reduced income in exchange for a ten-hour week or
four months of paid vacation per year to achieve that. It would
be inconvenient to the industrial system to do so, but
would make the opportunity of the individual to fashion his own
existence the primary social
concern, rather than the needs
of the system. All who speak of
liberty ought to approve.
Perhaps those most burdened by work in this age are those at the centre of the technostructure, of whom is
required a much greater commitment to his career than the production worker, both in terms
of hours and mental subordination to organisational purpose.
Throughout a long career his employer remains the focus of his existence, and then
in one day at the age of 65 he
loses the entire purpose of his
life.
Having become wholly habituated to group
activity, he is now alone. It is not a beautifully scripted
arrangement. Millions since the
dawn of man have led a less inspired existence but never on
comparable income. —p362
It is possible that a response is already visible. Business
schools are losing their distinction, and failing to attract the most able students. Business
courses and careers are increasingly held to be “excessively
disciplined, damaging to individuality, not worth the pay, or dull.”48)
We reach an interesting if speculative result.
Emancipation could be the
salvation of the industrial system. Its discipline
will be worse but only thus will it attract people who are
sufficiently good. —p363
The estate of higher education
is the organisation that is in
the best position to improve
this situation. Further, it now has the
power to do so, if it were confident enough to asset it. The industrial
system is entirely dependent on its output, yet this is little
recognised. Higher education has traditionally been dependent on
charity from the rich or from
government at the behest of the rich and remains obsequious to
its traditional benefactors. It must now recognise that it is of
vital important to the industrial system and is in a
position to make irresistible demands. The
most important of these should be that it be permitted to
reclaim control of its budgets. At present universities in the US are funded in an ad hoc manner,
with individual chairs and projects being financed by industry
and government, so that the
direction of research and the
balance of funding (particularly between the hard sciences and arts) is
dictated by the industrial system. Nobody refutes the current bias in funding towards
those subjects most closely beneficial to the industrial
system. By regaining control of its budgets, higher education
ought to offer equal support to students irrespective of their
chosen discipline. Those working in science departments who work
closely with industry and receive regular financing from a
variety of industrial sources
will identify closely with the
needs and ideology of the industrial system. The more independent of the industrial
system academia becomes, and the
more funding and emphasis is given to education with no
relevance to the industrial system, the more it will be possible for
students to develop a critical understanding of society and view
the industrial
system in perspective. If those in control in universities lead,
students will happily follow.
Education that accords with the needs of the industrial
system does not have a natural aspect of interest,
plausibility or importance. Much of it is dull. The learning that enables an
individual to participate effectively in the development of the monogramming toaster described
heretofore does not have an intrinsic air of social urgency.
Nor does the preparation or the manufacture of automobiles in
a world gorged with vehicles, or of a more potently, precisely
and diversely destructive missile in a world which has already
arranged extensively for its own incineration. Against this,
education that serves purely intellectual and aesthetic
interests, and encourages the
resulting detachment from the
goals of the industrial system, is by no means
unattractive. —p367-8
The price that
the industrial
system must pay for its people and the
conduct of its research is the
support of general enlightenment. —p367
At this moment there is a considerable if rather unfocused
atmosphere of dissent amongst younger people. As yet it has no
coherent political leadership. This ought to come from the scientific and educational
estate. It has the required
scepticism about the industrial system's objectives and
current trends in foreign policy under the
guidance of the industrial system. Since World War
II, scientists have already emerged as an independent political
force, especially where science imposes on foreign policy. The nuclear test ban treaty of 1963,
for example, would not have been achieved without the initiative of the scientific community.
General public and political awareness of the dangers of nuclear conflict, the desirability of détente
with the Soviet Union and the technical possibilities for
disarmament owes a great deal to the
scientific community. It owes very little to the military, diplomatic and industrial community. —p375
Economists are more or less useless in this role. Where economic
goals are of central importance, economists are useful — in a
wider debate that considers production against goals which
cannot by analysed using the
economist's toolbox, he ought to be marginalised, even if his
technical understanding is greater than those with a more
balanced perspective. Economists are the
natural ally of the industrial system. Recently, so has
the liberal been — to be a
liberal in recent times has meant to be an economic liberal,
espousing increased production, employment, management of
aggregate demand and greater equality of wages. These are no
longer an appropriate liberal platform — they need no liberal
advocacy to be enacted, the industrial system is more than
capable of fighting their corner unaided. The liberal economic programme, in
other words, has run its course — it is time to find a new one.
Members of the educational and
scientific estate have little confidence, and perceive their
role in society to be passive. This reflects their earlier
existence as a partly decorative appendage of the industrial
system. They were unable to challenge the
hand that fed in any substantial manner and an ideology grew up
to provide a rather more high-minded justification for their
enforced passivity:
Commanding power lay with the capitalist and entrepreneur.
It made sense not to affront it. If a righteous commitment to
science or art could be adduced as the
justification for this discretion, it was ideal — the equivalent of a priestly
indulgence for cowardice. —p377
Perhaps most importantly of all, within intellectual circles the belief persists that it is
intellectually corrupt to subordinate oneself to a wider
organisational structure for the
purposes of achieving a political result. Staunch individualism
makes such action distasteful. But it is absolutely necessary
for political efficacy. Persuasion is also important, and a task
of which the intellectual
establishment tends to tire quickly:
Condescension, impatience and the suffering ungladly of seeming
political obtuseness have all been damaging. Much worse has
been the failure of novitiate
members of the scientific and
educational estate, students in particular, to see that
political persuasion is a slow process and one that is not
served by jumping rapidly from one issue to another — from war
in Vietnam, to the
environment, to the Military-Industrial Complex, to the liberation of women — but
requires continued, patient and persistent effort on all
error. And most of all persuasion has been damaged by those
who have made violence a catharsis for impatience. The popular preference for
peaceful process may be regretted but it cannot be denied.
—p378
In the late nineteenth and
early twentieth century, discussion of the
future of capitalism is rife; the
present system was assumed to be an unstable and developing state. Such discussion no longer
continues. The industrial system in particular is
assumed to have reached some natural zenith, to remain as it
presently exists in perpetuity. This seems unlikely, but to
consider the ongoing changes in
the industrial
system would invite unwelcome analysis of various aspects of its
activity, not least the trend
of convergence between the
Soviet and Western economies.
It seems unlikely that the industrial system will be regarded
as independent for much longer. It has already been described as
the 'semi-nationalised' branch
of the economy.49)
Men will look back in amusement at the pretence that once caused
people to refer to General Dynamics and North American
Aviation and AT&T as private business. —p386
Once the industrial system is recognised as
being in the penumbra of the state,
it can no longer resist public goals on the basis of its claims to being
regulated or controlled by the
market. “There may well be danger in this association of public
and economic power. But it is less if it is recognised.”50)
Two primary questions frequently asked of an economic system
are: does it meet physical need and does it allow personal
liberty? The industrial system certainly meets the first. Concerns regarding the implications of the close collaboration of public
and economic power on personal liberty are sound. But it must be
recognised that the danger is
not of the all-powerful state seizing control of private
business, but an organic process in which the industrial
system has become gradually closer to the
state bureaucracy quite
willingly. Inherent in this process is a voluntary, even
enthusiastic, abdication of their freedom.
The president
of Republic Aviation is not much more likely in public to
speak critically, or even candidly, of
the Air Force than is
the head of a Soviet combinat of
the ministry to which he reports.
No modern head of
the Ford
Motor Company will ever react with
the
same pristine vigour to
the
presumed foolishness of Washington as did its founder…Manners
may be involved. But it would also be conceded that 'too much
is at stake'.
51)
—p389
The danger, instead, is that
belief becomes subordinated to the
industrial system — that the goals of society reflect its
needs too strongly. If we continue to hold the needs of the industrial
system as the highest social
goals then all other avenues of human endeavour will continue to
be subordinated to it, and we will continue to be managed as
consumers and as employees to fits its needs — as will
government policy and the
educational establishment. If the
industrial system is seen
instead as a part — and a diminishing part — of life, then the danger is much less great.
The foregoing
being so, we may, over time, come to see the industrial
system in fitting light as an essentially technical arrangement
for providing convenient goods and services in adequate volume.
Those who rise through its bureaucracy will so see themselves…
If other goals are strongly asserted, the
industrial system will fall into
its place as a detached and autonomous arm of the state,
but responsive to the larger
purposes of society.
We have seen wherein the chance
for salvation lies. The industrial system, in contrast with
its economic antecedents, is intellectually demanding. It brings
into existence, to serve its intellectual and scientific needs,
the community that, hopefully,
will reject is monopoly of social purpose. —p391